The elementary expression of the relative value of a single commodity, such as linen, in terms of the
commodity, such as gold, that plays the part of money, is the price-form of that commodity. The price-
form of the linen is therefore
20 yards of linen = 2 ounces of gold, or,
if 2 ounces of gold when coined are £2, 20 yards of linen = £2.
The difficulty in forming a concept of the money-form, consists in clearly comprehending the universal
equivalent form, and as a necessary corollary, the general form of value, form C. The latter is deducible
from form B, the expanded form of value, the essential component element of which, we saw, is form A,
20 yards of linen = 1 coat or x commodity A = y commodity B. The simple commodity-form is therefore
the germ of the money-form.
SECTION 4
THE FETISHISM OF COMMODITIES
AND THE SECRET THEREOF
A commodity appears, at first sight, a very trivial thing, and easily understood. Its analysis shows that
it is, in reality, a very queer thing, abounding in metaphysical subtleties and theological niceties. So far
as it is a value in use, there is nothing mysterious about it, whether we consider it from the point of view
that by its properties it is capable of satisfying human wants, or from the point that those properties are
the product of human labour. It is as clear as noon-day, that man, by his industry, changes the forms of
the materials furnished by Nature, in such a way as to make them useful to him. The form of wood, for
instance, is altered, by making a table out of it. Yet, for all that, the table continues to be that common,
every-day thing, wood. But, so soon as it steps forth as a commodity, it is changed into something transcendent.
It not only stands with its feet on the ground, but, in relation to all other commodities, it stands on its
head, and evolves out of its wooden brain grotesque ideas, far more wonderful than "table-turning" ever
was.
The mystical character of commodities does not originate, therefore, in their use-value. Just as little
does it proceed from the nature of the determining factors of value. For, in the first place, however varied
the useful kinds of labour, or productive activities, may be, it is a physiological fact, that they are functions
of the human organism, and that each such function, whatever may be its nature or form, is essentially
the expenditure of human brain, nerves, muscles, &c. Secondly, with regard to that which forms the
ground-work for the quantitative determination of value, namely, the duration of that expenditure, or the
quantity of labour, it is quite clear that there is a palpable difference between its quantity and quality. In
all states of society, the labour-time that it costs to produce the means of subsistence, must necessarily
be an object of interest to mankind, though not of equal interest in different stages of development.27
And lastly, from the moment that men in any way work for one another, their labour assumes a social
form.
Whence, then, arises the enigmatical character of the product of labour, so soon as it assumes the form
of commodities? Clearly from this form itself. The equality of all sorts of human labour is expressed
objectively by their products all being equally values; the measure of the expenditure of labour-power by
the duration of that expenditure, takes the form of the quantity of value of the products of labour; and
finally the mutual relations of the producers, within which the social character of their labour affirms
itself, take the form of a social relation between the products.
A commodity is therefore a mysterious thing, simply because in it the social character of men's labour
appears to them as an objective character stamped upon the product of that labour; because the relation
of the producers to the sum total of their own labour is presented to them as a social relation, existing
not between themselves, but between the products of their labour. This is the reason why the products
of labour become commodities, social things whose qualities are at the same time perceptible and imperceptible
by the senses. In the same way the light from an object is perceived by us not as the subjective excitation
of our optic nerve, but as the objective form of something outside the eye itself. But, in the act of seeing,
there is at all events, an actual passage of light from one thing to another, from the external object to